Here I am going
to tackle another anti-Molinist argument found on the Internet,
just for fun! The good news is this critique seems to explain the basics of
Molinism and middle knowledge accurately, which is not
always a given. However, his arguments against Molinism seem fairly
confused with respect to counterfactual semantics.
For a first
example, consider his argument that Molinism entails a contradiction in God’s
omniscience. He argues that in order for would-counterfactuals to be
contingently true, it must also be the case that God knows that these
counterfactuals “might not” be true. But, he claims, it is the case that
“might-not” and “would” are contradictory; hence, Molinism teaches that God
knows contradictions, which is absurd.
Presumably, this
author has seen the counterfactual square of opposition (or else holds that
these are contradictory for some other reason). Whatever the case may be, he is
correct: “Would” and “might not” counterfactuals are contradictories. However, he is confusing might-not
counterfactuals with the concept of contingency. As Craig and Moreland point
out,
‘Might’ counterfactuals should not be confused with subjunctive conditionals involving the word ‘could.’ ‘Could’ is taken to
express mere possibility and so is a constituent of a modal statement
expressing a possible truth. . . . The fact that something could happen . . .
does not imply that it might happen under those circumstances. ‘Might’ is more
restrictive than ‘could’ and indicates a genuine, live option under the
circumstances, not a bare logical possibility.[1]
This shows his
confusion. The author wants to say that another way of saying these would
counterfactuals are contingent is to say they might not occur, while also
admitting that such counterfactuals are contradictory. The former just isn’t so
on the technical semantics (even if it’s how we use it in ordinary language).
The next
criticism he has is against a “form of Molinism” whereby God exists outside of
time. It’s worth noting that someone can hold to God’s timelessness or some
other view and believe Molinism. If there were to be a significant problem for
holding both Craig’s model and Molinism, one could jettison the model and
retain Molinism, perhaps. He writes of Craig’s view of Molinism, “What I do
take issue with is God knowing those possibilities based on what we do because
this would render God’s knowledge contingent on us and therefore God would be
‘learning.’”
It’s not clear
why he says, “therefore,” as no rule of inference will derive this conclusion
from that premise. I can repair the argument to be valid: If God’s knowledge is
contingent, then he is learning; God’s knowledge is contingent; therefore, he
is learning. But we’d still need some argument that the major premise is true,
given Molinism. I have no idea what that argument is.
His last set of
critiques is that Molinism is problematic because it denies determinism. But of
course, anyone who does not already embrace determinism shouldn’t be convinced
by this. His argument is that there seem to be certain things that are true in
all possible worlds God could actualize regarding supposedly free choices in the
libertarian sense, so that really he has to embrace some kind of determinism.
But this is
multiply confused. First, if some fact F is necessarily
true, it is not theologically causally determined (or, it is so only in light
of its logical necessity). Unless he believes in some kind of modal universal
possibilism, if something is necessarily true not even God himself could change
that truth value. Second, he writes out his modal argument purely in English
sentences; if he had symbolized it, he would have seen the argument commits the
very same modal fallacy he earlier recognizes as fallacious. One can still see
it in the English itself. Here it is:
1.
Simultaneity
is transitive (if A happens simultaneously with B, and C happens simultaneously
with B, then, necessarily, A happens simultaneously with C).
2.
Apply
to middle knowledge: if A takes place at t1, and this is simultaneous with
God’s knowledge, then God’s knowledge of A is simultaneous with C.
3.
Therefore,
A is necessarily taking place simultaneously with C.
But this is just
the well-known modal fallacy. The problem starts with the initial formulation
itself. The transitive property is not that if A=B and C=B, necessarily A=C.
It’s rather, “Necessarily, if A=B and C=B, then A=C.” Here’s a brief example.
Consider height relations. Based on the meaning of the term, they use
transitive relations. So, necessarily, if Jim is as tall as Dan, and Brad is as tall as Dan, then Jim and Brad are as tall as Dan. But who wants to
thereby infer that it’s a necessary truth that Jim and Brad are as tall as Dan? Who wants to say there is some mysterious truth of logic that dictates the
relative heights of these three men?
Finally, this is
confused as to Craig’s model of time with respect to middle knowledge. The content
of middle knowledge comes logically prior to the creative decree. On Craig’s
model (which he is ostensibly critiquing), crucially, there is no time at all; this is why it is referred to as coming logically prior to the creative decree.
Thus, there is no simultaneity to speak of anyway.
In conclusion,
this author seems at least relatively familiar with Molinism and some issues
surrounding Craig’s work, but not familiar enough to avoid some serious
misunderstandings.
EDIT: Changed example for Jim, Brad, and Dan to better reflect the transitivity.
EDIT: Changed example for Jim, Brad, and Dan to better reflect the transitivity.
[1] J.P. Moreland and
William Lane Craig, Philosophical
Foundations for a Christian Worldview (Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2003),
53.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Please remember to see the comment guidelines if you are unfamiliar with them. God bless and thanks for dropping by!