In the Calvinist/non-Calvinist
dialectic over whether or not God wants people to be saved, the following often
occurs:
Claim: God doesn’t want some people to be saved, on Calvinism. This is
because he could cause them to believe if he really wanted to, but he doesn’t.
Response: But you have the same problem. On your view, God still has the
power to cause people to believe, but he doesn’t, because he values free will.
We have the same kind of response: God could save everyone, but he values
something else more. For you, it’s human freedom, and for us, it’s his own
glory.
It seems to me this response misses a
crucial nuance that I’d like to explore.
When the non-Calvinist asserts that, on
Calvinism, God doesn’t want some people to be saved, what she is really claiming (or at least what she should be claiming) is that God doesn’t
want some people to believe. It is
this key distinction in the dispute that will make all the difference. What
does it mean to “believe” in Jesus? Does it mean to believe in his existence?
Well, sure. What about his claims to divinity, and his resurrection? Of course.
But it also means much more than these mere intellectual states. It is an
active trust in God for life and salvation (just ask yourself—or a Calvinist—if
someone is really a believer who has no interest in trusting God or following
Christ at the time of their supposed conversion).
But this kind of trust, love, and
discipleship can only be entered into freely. I suspect that, at bottom, most
Calvinists would agree (on certain conditions, no doubt—but conditions not
needed at present to agree). Non-Calvinists in the debate tend to believe in
the thesis of incompatibilism—that causal determinism is incompatible with
freedom—and as such, causal determinism is incompatible with freely entering
into a love and trust relationship with Jesus Christ. Calvinists often, though
not always, affirm compatibilism—the thesis that causal determinism is
compatible with free action—and so causal determinism will be compatible with
freely entering into such a relationship.
Now we can see the difference between the
initial claim and the response, and why the response (given by people such as
John Piper) doesn’t have the intended force. It’s because the answer is
“no”—God cannot force someone to freely do something, any more than he can
create a married bachelor or lie or will himself not to exist, etc. The whole
idea of salvation presumes a free choice to participate in sin such that one
needs salvation.
Now on the non-Calvinist view, God could
have created creatures without any free will, such that none would ever go
wrong. But then these wouldn’t be humans (and plausibly wouldn’t have been made
in the image of God); they would be something else entirely. Notice the
response loses force if we amend it to, “Yes, but on your view, God could have
refrained from creating humans and no one would be lost;” the lack of creation
is not symmetrical to securing universal salvation. The fact remains that on
the Calvinist view, God could secure a free response of salvific belief for
everyone, and simply does not do it.