I was thinking
today about a common theme in discussing what skeptics and non-believers may
say if confronted by God in the afterlife. A typical retort is that they did
not have enough evidence or reason to believe in God, and so did not know God
existed or of their need for repentance. This relies heavily on the traditional
analysis of knowledge as “justified, true belief.”[1]
The argument, then, would look like this:
1.
If
one does not know he ought to do x,
then it is not the case that he ought to do x.
2.
One
does not know he ought to do x.
3.
Therefore,
it is not the case that he ought to do x.
The argument
seems straightforward enough. The unbeliever does not, by definition, believe
in God’s existence and so does not, by definition, believe he must repent. If
he does not believe these things, then by the traditional analysis, he does not
know these things (since belief is a necessary condition). Thus, the unbeliever
is not actually obligated to respond to the Gospel, for one can hardly know
what he thinks is untrue, and so he’s off the hook!
The typical
Christian response is to accept (1) and deny (2). Romans 1 and 10, Psalm 19,
and other passages suggest strongly that everyone knows there is a God. Thus,
there really are no such things as atheists, in the strict sense—everyone
believes or knows, deep down, even if it is suppressed to the point of the
subconscious. While I think this response, if carefully nuanced, can get to the
truth of the matter (that is, I agree with the Bible), it’s not always helpful
to tell the atheist what he “really believes.” Rather, I intend to attack (1).
While initially
plausible, I think (1) is not impervious to objection. Consider a person who is
responsible for being in his current predicament, even though he cannot now
alter his current state. That person, if in circumstances in which he ought to
refrain from performing some action, still ought to refrain from performing
that action, if he was responsible for being in the particular state he is in
now. Take a drug addict, and assume one ought not to abuse drugs. Suppose
further, as has been argued, that there is at least possibly some circumstance
such that, were a drug addict sufficiently addicted, he could not now refrain
from shooting up with heroin (without some external intervention). In this case
the drug addict, if he chose to use drugs of his own volition and became
addicted through that free choice or series of free choices, is responsible for
his current predicament. Additionally, it is plausible that he is morally
responsible—not just for the initial acts, but for the subsequent acts, and the
act within the situation that now confronts him. In other words, even though
the drug addict fails to have now a
necessary condition for being such that he ought to refrain from abusing drugs,
he nonetheless still ought to refrain from abusing drugs—because he is
completely responsible for being in the situation in which he finds himself.[2]
So how can we
apply this to our situation with the unbeliever? It seems we could say that if
an atheist is responsible for his initial state of unbelief,[3]
then he is responsible for his current state as well. So, if we have someone
who decides to walk away from Christianity, or will not accept it, and they
chose that state, then even if they do not now
believe (or even find themselves unable to believe!), it was within their power
to believe and so are still obligated to trust and repent. Now it’s obvious
that a non-believer can dispute our account here; but this is not the point.
The point is that (1) is not nearly as obvious as a first glance may suggest,
and is even plausibly false.
Plausibly, we
can capture the intuitive force of (1) as:
1’. If
one is not responsible for his current state of not knowing he ought to do x, then it is not the case that he ought
to do x.
2’. One is not responsible for his
current state of not knowing he ought to do x.
3.
Therefore,
it is not the case that he ought to do x.
(1’) and
plausible instances of (2’) seem right. But now notice that this is not the
state most non-believers we’ve been discussing find themselves in. They usually
are responsible for not believing the
Gospel. While some may claim that no beliefs are chosen, I find this hard to
believe (and if they’re right, I couldn’t have chosen to believe it anyway). I
think at least some beliefs are chosen, and even if they aren’t, the argument
plausibly needs only that sense of responsibility that anyone would have about
anything anyone has concerning their current states and/or formation of
character. But again, a skeptic need not accept this alternative account in
order for us to show that the original account, and hence the original excuse,
fails.
[1] Let’s leave to one side
Gettier cases or attempted counterexamples for the sake of argument.
[2] This has some
interesting implications for “ought-implies-can” which I will, for now, leave
to the reader to work out.
[3] Here we may want to distinguish
between states of infants and states of what I shall call “responsible
knowers,” which will coincide with a state of moral responsibility. I will
appeal to this latter state, though I will not endeavor here to figure out when
that begins.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Please remember to see the comment guidelines if you are unfamiliar with them. God bless and thanks for dropping by!