The
following is another anti-Molinist argument I’d like to look at today. It might
get a little technical, especially since after the argument is made, I list it
in quasi-symbolic form. I also stole the title from William Lane Craig!
If Molinism is true, God
knows that some proposition P (“S will take A”) is true in W.
If God knows
that P is true in W, P is true in W. If P is true in W, then proposition Q (“P
is true in W”) is true in all possible worlds. If Q is true in all possible
worlds, then Q is necessarily true. If Q is necessarily true, it is not
possible that Q is false. If it is not possible that Q is false, it is not
possible that S will not take A in C.
Therefore, If Molinism is true, it is not
possible that S will not take A in C.
1.
If
M, then K.
2.
If
K, then P in W.
3.
If P
in W, then Q in all possible worlds.
4.
If Q
in all possible worlds, then N.
5.
If
N, then ~ possibly ~Q.
6.
If ~
possibly ~Q, then ~ possibly ~P.
7.
If
M, then ~possibly ~P.
First, I’d like
to point out that Molinism and God’s knowledge of propositions are incidental
to this argument. That is, while it applies, you could simply start from
premise 3. If you do, what you get is the conclusion that “If S will take A,
then it is impossible that S will not take A.” So this argument, if sound, and
by the rules of logic, means that if anything is true at any world whatsoever,
then it is necessarily true. Perhaps this is the objector’s point; perhaps the
objector is committed to the proposition that everything whatsoever is
determined or fated in this way. Or perhaps the objector did not notice this
point, and instead is committed to the point that nothing whatsoever is true.
Or else, finally, the objector just didn’t realize this at all, and the
argument is unsound. I don’t think it’s good enough for us to leave it at that;
I want to examine why it is unsound.
Premise (1) is pretty solid. That states that if Molinism is true, then God knows some particular proposition,
symbolized by “K” (which particular proposition we are calling “P,” and whose
content is that “S will do A”[1])
is true in some particular world W. (2) stays, since it says that if God knows
that P is true in W, then P is true in W (we’ll call this proposition [that “P
is true in W”] “Q”).
So what about
(3)? Is that true? I think so. It just says that if P is true in W (Q), then Q
is necessarily true. Why? Let's say the proposition
represented by P is specifically that “Randy writes on his blog on September
23, 2014,” and that P (so defined) is true in the actual world, which we will
call W-147 (because, why not?).
We
can thereby represent a new proposition, called Q. Q states:
Q.
P is true in W-147,
Which
is just equivalent to Q-translated, which is:
Q-translated:
“Randy writes on his blog on September 23, 2014” is true in W-147.
Now
suppose we move to world W-148, which is a very similar world to ours, except
kangaroos don't exist (because, why not?). Now let's examine all of the truths
there are in W-148 (because we have time!). What about Q? Is Q true here?
Remember, Q's content is not about
W-148, and so nothing in W-148 can have any effect on Q's truth-value. What is
sufficient for the truth of Q can be found only
in W-147. But since it's true in W-147, and this is an objective truth, it will
be true in W-148 that:
In
W-147, “Randy writes on his blog on September 23, 2014” is true; which is only
really to say that:
Q-translated:
“Randy writes on his blog on September 23, 2014” is true in W-147; which is
really just saying:
Q.
P is true in W-147,
and
the process can be repeated in any world you wish, which gains us a necessary
truth. But this is really no more controversial, in my opinion, than the fact
that whatever is possible is necessarily possible. That is, if something is
logically possible, then its impossibility is impossible; if something is
logically possible, then at no world is it impossible, for impossibility
stretches across worlds (that's just what it means to be impossible--not
possible at any worlds; but if it is possible at a world (in the logical
sense), then it's possible at every world). Anyway, just as nearly no one is
bothered by every possible truth's entailing some necessary truth (namely, that
it's possible), so no one should be bothered by something like Q, in my
opinion.
(4)
and (5) are analyses of necessity, and so I think they should stay.
But why think
(6) is true? Q just is the proposition “P is true in W.” What (6) does,
however, is distribute the necessity of the entire
claim “P is true in W” to a particular part of the claim (namely, P). But
it is the well-known and oft-committed modal fallacy to infer the necessity of
a particular part of a claim from the necessity of the entire claim itself.
Here’s a quick and easy example of Right Necessity (RN) and Wrong Necessity
(WN):
RN. Necessarily,
either everyone is six feet tall or not everyone is six feet tall.
WN. (Since not
everyone is six feet tall) Necessarily, not everyone is six feet tall.
But perhaps
their usage of this fallacy is even worse than what has just transpired. For
consider the exact nature of the fallacy:
WN1. If
necessarily “P is true in W,” then necessarily P.
But this
inference seems crazy! There are plenty of counterexamples to this inference.
Let’s take what most assume is a contingent truth: that the Solar System has
nine planets.[2]
Since in our world W, the Solar System does
have nine planets (get off my back about it!), it will be true in every world
that “The Solar system has nine planets in W.” We should hardly infer, on this
basis, then, that it’s a logically necessary truth that what we call the Solar
System should have nine planets! If you need an even less controversial
example, take the number of dust particles on the moon. It’s true that the
number of dust particles the moon will ever have in its entire history of this
world entails “The number of dust particles the moon will ever have in its
entire history of W is true in W,” where “W” is the actual world and some
number is represented by the long introductory clause. That entire claim is a
necessary truth, but who wants to thereby infer that the exact number of dust
particles on the moon is logically necessary? Perhaps someone, but not most of
us.
So there you
have it. (6) commits the modal fallacy, and the argument for determinism from
anything’s being true at all (which just so happens to apply to Molinism, since
it claims things are true at worlds) fails.
[1] As a non-trivial point,
it should be noted that this “will” language is entirely wrongheaded. We should
try to use tenseless language to describe truths at possible worlds, since the
vast majority of possible worlds are never actualized (in fact, only one of
them is), and thus there is no future “will” to speak of in these worlds.
[2] I know, I know. Pluto
is still a planet in my heart!
No comments:
Post a Comment
Please remember to see the comment guidelines if you are unfamiliar with them. God bless and thanks for dropping by!